Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-m8qmq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T04:05:04.165Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The person as moralist account and its alternatives

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 October 2010

Joshua Knobe
Affiliation:
Program in Cognitive Science and Department of Philosophy, Yale University, New Haven, CT 06520-8306. joshua.knobe@yale.eduhttp://pantheon.yale.edu/~jk762/

Abstract

The commentators offer helpful suggestions at three levels: (1) explanations for the particular effects discussed in the target article; (2) implications of those effects for our understanding of the role of moral judgment in human cognition; and (3) more theoretical questions about the overall relationship between ordinary cognition and systematic science. The present response takes up these three issues in turn.

Type
Author's Response
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alicke, M. (1992) Culpable causation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 63:368–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alicke, M. (2008) Blaming badly. Journal of Cognition and Culture 8:179–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guglielmo, S. & Malle, B. F. (in press) Can unintended side-effects be intentional? Resolving a controversy over intentionality and morality. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin.Google Scholar
Hindriks, F. (2008) Intentional action and the praise-blame asymmetry. Philosophical Quarterly 58:630–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, C. & Knobe, J. (2009) Cause and norm. Journal of Philosophy 106(11):587612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A., Knobe, J. & Bloom, P. (2009) Disgust sensitivity predicts intuitive disapproval of gays. Emotion 9(3):435–39.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Knobe, J. (2007) Reason explanation in folk psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31:90107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloy, R. & Byrne, R. (2000) Counterfactual thinking about controllable events. Memory and Cognition 28:1071–78.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mercier, H. & Sperber, D. (forthcoming) Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences.Google Scholar
Nadelhoffer, T. (2006a) Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: Some problems for jury impartiality. Philosophical Explorations 9:203–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
N'gbala, A. & Branscombe, N. R. (1995). Mental simulation and causal attribution: When simulating an event does not affect fault assignment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 31:139–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nichols, S. & Ulatowski, J. (2007) Intuitions and individual differences: The Knobe effect revisited. Mind and Language 22:346–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pellizzoni, S., Girotto, V. & Surian, L. (2010) Beliefs and moral valence affect intentionality attributions: The case of side effects. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1:201209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phelan, M. & Sarkissian, H. (2008) The folk strike back; or, why you didn't do it intentionally, though it was bad and you knew it. Philosophical Studies 138(2):291–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roxborough, C. & Cumby, J. (2009) Folk psychological concepts: Causation. Philosophical Psychology 22:205–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sverdlik, S. (2004) Intentionality and moral judgments in commonsense thought about action. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 24:224–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, J. C. & Bengson, J. (2009) Asymmetries in judgments of responsibility and intentional action. Mind and Language 24(1):2450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, L., Cushman, F., Adolphs, R., Tranel, D. & Hauser, M. (2006) Does emotion mediate the effect of an action's moral status on its intentional status? Neuropsychological evidence. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6:291304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar