Your email was sent successfully. Check your inbox.

An error occurred while sending the email. Please try again.

Proceed reservation?

Export
  • 1
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1984
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 30 ( 1984), p. 49-71
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 30 ( 1984), p. 49-71
    Abstract: When Plato's and Aristotle's views on poetry are juxtaposed, it is usually for the purpose of contrast. Nowhere does the contrast seem to be so sharp as in the case of tragedy, by which both philosophers, agreeing in this at least, rightly meant Homer's Iliad as well as the plays of the Attic genre specifically given the name. While Plato made tragedy the target of his most fervent attacks on poetry, Aristotle devoted the major part of the Poetics to a reconsideration of the genre, in a sympathetic attempt, it is normally agreed, to defend it against Plato's strictures, and to restore to it some degree of valuable independence. The apparently fundamental opposition between the philosophers’ responses to tragedy can be regarded as expressive of divergent presuppositions about the status of poetry as a whole in relation to other components of culture: on the one side, the presupposition of Platonic moralism, by which poetry is subjected to judgement in terms of values, both cognitive and moral, which lie outside itself; and, on the other, of Aristotelian formalism, according to which autonomy can be established for poetry by turning the criteria of poetic excellence into standards internal and intrinsic to poetry's own forms. As Aristotle himself puts the point, in one of the Poetics ’ more suggestive pronouncements, ‘correctness in poetry is not the same as correctness in politics or in any other art.’ Here, as often, an implicit response to Plato can be detected.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1984
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 2
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 2001
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 47 ( 2001), p. 81-102
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 47 ( 2001), p. 81-102
    Abstract: The idea of examining law as a cultural phenomenon seems surprisingly underappreciated – especially by legal scholars. Black-letter law, sociology of law, Eigentum und Besitz , law and life, life and law (which of you imitates the other?), all rank among the usual suspects in professional discourse, to the evident exclusion of law as culture. This is of course potentially a broad topic, even if we limit it to the assumptions or assertions about law found in literary discourse, an area of study that naturally requires no small degree of non-legal expertise. That may be the difficulty. A few exceptions, whom I admire and hope to emulate – for their ambitious, pioneering spirit, have spied an opportunity here. Perhaps the best-known example of this approach is John Crook, who writes: … legal talk and terminology seem rather more frequent and more at home in Roman literature than in ours. Legal terms of art could be used for literary metaphor, could be the foundation of stage jokes or furnish analogy in philosophical discussion. And a corollary of this is that many a passage of Latin belles lettres needs a knowledge of the law for its comprehension. Crook, disappointingly, lets it go at that, failing to fulfil the promise of boundless opportunity expressed in the last sentence.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 2001
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 3
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1973
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 19 ( 1973), p. 9-34
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 19 ( 1973), p. 9-34
    Abstract: On re-reading Dio of Prusa's Euboicus , I formed the impression that his ideas on manual labour and on the respectability of occupations open to the poor are somewhat different from those conventionally adopted by Greeks and Romans of the upper class, to which Dio belonged. Part 1 of this paper discusses these ideas in the Euboicus and in some related works of Dio. It will inter alia afford some conjectural support to von Arnim's hypothesis that the Euboicus was delivered at Rome. Probably Dio's attitude was influenced by his experience in exile, when he had known what it was to be poor and had even propounded Cynic opinions. But the Euboicus is a work of his old age (VII. 1), and his conduct after his restoration to his home in A.D. 96 was conspicuously non-Cynic. If then we find some indication that he was also indebted to some previous theorizing on appropriate occupations for the free poor, we need not think of a Cynic model; indeed we should not, for the Cynics were little given to the kind of casuistry involved. In Part I some evidence will be found that Dio was also influenced by Stoic teaching, and in Part II it will be argued that his discussion of the way in which the poor could decently earn their living goes back to Stoic works on practical morality of the kind illustrated by Panaetius' treatise On Appropriate Action ; however, Dio's ideas are not those of the Middle Stoa and more probably derive from Cleanthes or Chrysippus. In this connection I take Cicero, de officiis 1. 150 f., to represent the views of Panaetius, and as I have found that this interpretation can be contested, I have tried to justify it in the Appendix.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1973
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 4
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1960
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 6 ( 1960), p. f1-f1
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 6 ( 1960), p. f1-f1
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1960
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 5
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1978
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 24 ( 1978), p. 68-91
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 24 ( 1978), p. 68-91
    Abstract: The twentieth century has been so begrudging to Timon of Phlius that he could be forgiven for identifying himself with his misanthropic namesake. About a hundred and fifty of his ‘glänzenden Sillen’ (the phrase is Wilamowitz's) survive, but in Albin Lesky's Geschichte der griechischen Literatur Timon gets only a third of the space devoted to Anaximander from whom we possess one possible sentence. Serious work on Timon largely came to a stop with Hermann Diels who edited the fragments and testimonia in Poetarum philosophorum fragmenta (Berlin, 1901), a book which is as difficult to come by as the older and much fuller study of Timon by C. Wachsmuth in Sillographorum Graecorum reliquiae (Leipzig, 1885). In spite of his skilful parody of Homer and his Aristophanic versatility in language (some sixty neologisms, many of them comic formations, occur in the fragments), Timon has been ignored by those who give such generous attention to Hellenistic poetry. Many fragments raise at least one major textual difficulty. A new edition and literary study of the material is badly needed.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1978
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 6
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1997
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 42 ( 1997), p. b1-b1
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 42 ( 1997), p. b1-b1
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1997
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 7
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1989
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 35 ( 1989), p. b1-b1
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 35 ( 1989), p. b1-b1
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1989
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 8
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 2004
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 50 ( 2004), p. 92-120
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 50 ( 2004), p. 92-120
    Abstract: Debate in the Iliad – what form it takes, what significance that might have, whether or not it even exists – has been a matter of some controversy. One approach has been to examine debate in terms of a formal social context and to extrapolate from this some kind of political or – according to other accounts – pre-political community that the Iliad preserves. Scholars have, however come up with very different ideas about how to describe that society, how to interpret that depiction, or whether such attempts are even fruitful. An alternative approach focuses on the form of the speeches and analyses them as the production of thesis and antithesis: in these terms the cut-and-thrust of debate is understood as a form of proto-rhetorical theory. All this seems far removed from debate as it is represented in the narrative, which is the subject of this paper. I begin with four preliminary propositions. Previous approaches have tended to homogenise different scenes of debate, with little regard to differences in structure or context.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 2004
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 9
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1980
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 26 ( 1980), p. 12-66
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 26 ( 1980), p. 12-66
    Abstract: Three words of the Aristophanic lexicon, λαικάζειν, λαικαστής and λαικάστρια, are not fully explained by the contexts in which they occur. The remains of ancient learning known to scholars of the sixteenth century contained no clear and unambiguous doctrine about them. A considerable amount of fresh material however has accumulated during recent centuries. The Latinists W. Heraeus and A. E. Housman studied what was available to them around the years 1914 and 1930 respectively and came to firm conclusions but without persuading many students of Aristophanes' comic scripts in particular or of the Greek language in general. G. P. Shipp has recently drawn attention to a third century A.D. document, first published as long ago as 1925, which has the verb in a context leaving little doubt about the user's meaning. This paper attempts to consider systematically the evidence now available and to make clear how Aristophanes and other Athenians of the fifth, fourth and third centuries B.C. used the word group. It is argued that the verb remained alive among some speakers of Greek without change of function until very late and that Housman's explanation of the Aristophanic passages was correct.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1980
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
  • 10
    Online Resource
    Online Resource
    Cambridge University Press (CUP) ; 1988
    In:  Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society Vol. 34 ( 1988), p. 77-103
    In: Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge University Press (CUP), Vol. 34 ( 1988), p. 77-103
    Abstract: In this paper I will discuss what Aristotle has to say on the relation between τὸ ἕν and τὸ ὄν. Stated briefly the relation is that τὸ ἕν and τὸ ὄν are (a) transcendental predicates: each applies in all the categories; (b) convertible predicates: each implies the other and adds nothing to the other. For Met. 1003b23–4 claims that being and unity are one and the same thing in that they are implied in each other, τὸ ὂν καὶ τὸ ἕν ταὐτὸν καὶ μία φύσις τῶι ἀκολουθεîν ἀλλήλοις. This is clearly meant to apply in every category, since the convertibility claim is functioning as a premiss in an argument whose conclusion is that there are exactly as many types of being as of unity. At Met. 1061a17–18 there is an equally explicit statement of convertibility, καὶ γὰρ εἰ μὴ ταὐτὸν ἄλλο δ' ἐστίν, ἀντιστρέφει γε· τό τε γὰρ ἓν καὶ ὄν πως, τό τε ὄν ἔν. I will try to say more precisely what these claims mean, and come to some view on their philosophical plausibility. There are a number of reasons for discussing these topics. First, it is a prolegomenon to a comprehensive discussion of all those predicates which came to be thought of as convertible and transcendental.
    Type of Medium: Online Resource
    ISSN: 0068-6735 , 2053-5899
    RVK:
    Language: English
    Publisher: Cambridge University Press (CUP)
    Publication Date: 1988
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 2649569-7
    detail.hit.zdb_id: 1483586-1
    SSG: 6,12
    Library Location Call Number Volume/Issue/Year Availability
    BibTip Others were also interested in ...
Close ⊗
This website uses cookies and the analysis tool Matomo. Further information can be found on the KOBV privacy pages